Sunday, January 7, 2018

review -- I Am Not a Brain by Markus Gabriel and Consciouness: a very short introduction by Susan Blackmore

For many people, philosophy is a swamp, a madhouse, an ear-splitting cave filled with pointless,  hair-splitting, logic-chopping argumentation. That may be true, but periodically we all find ourselves falling into that swamp, that madhouse, that cave. In the early days of computers, digital technology lured us in, asking us to ponder whether robots will one day look us in the eye with human-like intelligence. Much hair-splitting and argumentation ensued, with no clear results. Today the philosophical abyss opens again, thanks to sweeping claims made by neuroscience, which believes it has found the answers to some big questions. Does a mind exist or only a brain? What exactly is our inner life, our consciousness? Where does consciousness take place? How can something immaterial make connections with the material body? Is there any reality to the self, the ego, our feeling that we are the agents of our own actions? With recent discoveries about how our thoughts and actions depend on the brain, how can we believe that we have free will? Most of these questions go back many hundreds of years, and the philosophers who took them on, Descartes, Leibniz, Kant, Russell, and others disagreed with each other in a thousand ways. Perhaps we are nearing a day now when science will provide the final answers.

In her clear and concise monograph, Consciousness : a very short introduction, psychologist Susan J. Blackmore outlines the scientific findings on consciousness. The experiments and case studies she presents are entertaining and thought-provoking, as they seek evidence in dreaming, synaesthesia, multiple personalities, ouijah boards, out-of-body and near-death experiences, animal consciousness, and so on. Even ordinary experiences seem to yield insights. For example, since people can commute to or from work for half an hour or more and have no memory of doing it, they must have somehow been conscious to navigate and obey traffic signals. Yet it’s not a normal sort of consciousness that leaves no trace in memory immediately afterwards. In the 1960s one of the most startling discoveries was made when brains were scanned of subjects performing very simple physical operations, such as moving an arm. Parts of the brain associated with preparing for physical movement were found to be activated a full half-second before the conscious subject thought they had decided to move the arm. This raised grave doubts as to whether we are really agents of our own actions, whether the self exists, and whether we have free will.

Dubious Conclusions

Philosophical questions are ubiquitous in Blackmore’s account. Again and again as she describes what science says about consciousness, she bumps into the problem of explaining the connection between what scientists observe from the outside and what we as individuals experience from the inside, and she admits repeatedly that she cannot give an answer. She uncovers indications that seem to undermine the common sense view but never quite gets to proofs. To cover the gap she invokes future discoveries—coming ”soon,” she says—when our technologies will be more advanced. Perhaps we will even discover the elusive “neural correlates of consciousness.” In the meantime, however, Blackmore does not bind herself to the evidence at hand, instead deeming the preliminary indications to be, likely, the whole truth. This leads to some peculiar theses. The mind, she believes, that is, the self, the entire mental world, is an illusion, and we ought to live dutifully keeping in mind that it is all an illusion: “This is tough, but I think it gets easier with practice,” she says, without offering any tips on how it is to be done. Free will is also an illusion, according to Blackmore, but, since studies have shown that rejecting belief in free will increases one’s tendency to depression, we should live “as if” we believe in free will. Her book is an excellent introduction to the science of consciousness, but when it addresses ancient philosophical questions, it founders badly.


A Critique of Neurocentrism

In the recently published I Am Not A Brain: Philosophy of Mind for the Twenty-First Century German philosopher Markus Gabriel takes the philosophical questions head-on in a multi-pronged attack on what he calls “neurocentrism,” the blurring, even the identification, of mind and brain. The claims of today’s neuroscientists and psychologists, he believes, are riddled with omissions, incoherence, and bad logic. In a book sometimes dense with argument, sometimes light and spacious, making its points with references to Fargo and Doctor Who almost as often as Kant and Hegel, Gabriel subjects the pillars of neurocentrism to close scrutiny, picking away at their logic, exposing their presumptions, and investigating alternative explanations.

One of the most powerful images driving us toward the neurocentric, materialistic view is that of a machine-like universe consisting of nothing but particles and energy, all locked into a chain of causality stretching from the beginning of the universe until its end. Because our brains belong to that realm, and because the brain is the originator, apparently, of all thought, it is argued that we are mere automata (as are all other conscious creatures), our entire mental world functioning beyond our control, inescapable and foreordained. Gabriel attempts to weaken the force of that image, pointing out, for example, that the current state of physics is not a closed, finished system: it cannot yet integrate gravity with quantum mechanics, it has no account of dark matter and dark energy, and causality seems vitiated by probabilities. However, he accepts the validity of determinism—as applied to the world of matter. Taking it further, though, is, he says, to over-extend one model of explanation over the entire cosmos.

The World Does Not Exist

Gabriel’s most unusual argument was presented at length in a previous book (and TEDTalk) entitled Why the World Does Not Exist. It is not possible, he believes, to step outside everything that exists, comprehend it all at once in a God-like glance, and thus see both the entire contents and the absolute limits of “the world” or “the universe.” That’s what materialists think they have done when they declare that only matter and energy exist. But why only matter and energy? Do numbers not exist? The rules of logic? How about facts? Or the Federal Republic of Germany, Hamlet (the play, not the physical words printed on the page), relationships, democracy, love? Gabriel contends that it is a mistake to assert that everything that exists belongs to a single class and that everything that exists cannot be comprehended in a single frame of reference. Instead, he wants us to accept a countless number of what he calls “fields of sense,” so that, just as it is meaningful and true to say that chairs and rainbows exist, in other fields of sense it can be meaningful and true to say that principles exist, or friendship or even Ebenezer Scrooge. Of course, Gabriel’s main interest in this argument is to clear the way for the mind and its cognates to be recognized as existing just as surely as atoms.

A chapter is devoted to each of consciousness, self-consciousness, the self, and freedom, as he both deals with various reductionist views of the mind and develops his own position, which he calls New Realism. Much of it is the common sense view of the mind — that it is real (although not a mysterious ‘substance’ and not existing apart from the brain); the true originator of many, but not all, of our actions; and operating with free will, even as it is subject to unconscious processes. He offers a tricky notion, though, for the defining function of the mind, which he takes to be its ability to think creatively about itself, ceaselessly to form conceptions of itself. At least part of what this means is our ability to imagine our own identities, as a Christian, for example, or a German, a patriot, a gift to the opposite sex (the mind can make errors about itself, of course) or a plaything of fate. This feature he takes to be absolutely crucial: “The human mind does not have a reality that is independent of its self-images.” Because a self-image has consequences in action and engenders a multiplicity of further thoughts, Gabriel believes it is important to push back against neurocentrism’s false image of the mind as illusory and unfree.

Here and there Gabriel raps the knuckles of some incidental figures, such as Richard Dawkins for his thesis that the human is no more than an elaborate biological mechanism devoted to the single purpose of passing on genes, Freud for his idea that the mind is enslaved to the libido, and Silicon Valley types who anticipate cyborgs and a future when an individual’s human experience can be uploaded to a computer, a network, or a USB stick. “Darwinitis” comes under fire for invoking a remote, mythical past to explain concepts such as egoism, altruism, good, and evil in terms of the struggle for survival and genetic transmission rather than accepting the historical development of these concepts, already so well documented in culture.

The Other Sciences of the Mind

“Nothing is more human than the wish to deny one’s humanity,” wrote philosopher Stanley Cavell. Again and again Gabriel sees attempts to reduce our humanity to something other than, and always less than, human. The German word for the humanities, he points out, Geisteswissenschaften, means “sciences of the mind” and consists of subjects such as philosophy, history, musicology, linguistics, and theatre studies. There, he thinks, is where we learn the most about the human mind. Neuroscience undoubtedly helps us understand the biological phenomena without which, of course, there is no mental life. But it has not proven that we are identical with our brains or provided satisfactory explanations of mental phenomena. More important, it seems unlikely ever to provide the level of insight into ourselves that we find beyond the sciences in figures like Sophocles, de Tocqueville, Proust, or Niebuhr.


I Am Not A Brain could be much better focused. As it shifts from topic to topic, the connections can be fuzzy, sometimes leaving the feeling of a miscellany, as if portions were patched together from notebooks. Nevertheless, it is very stimulating, invites repeated readings, and provokes hours of reflection. Written with the lay reader in mind without sacrificing intellectual rigour, it offers a bracing reminder to keep our guard up against, not neuroscience itself, but its philosophical pretensions.